A rough sketch of what I wanted to write about the Weathermen in the Demagoguery book

building blown up by weathermen

When I was working on the demagoguery book, I wanted to include pieces all over the political spectrum, including something by an author I really liked (Muir) and something from the radical left. Length made me cut the discussion of Muir’s “Hetch Hetchy Valley.” (At the time, I thought it would be part of my next book project. It’s now moved to the one after this at the earliest.) And I also spent some time thinking I’d write about the Weathermen, but writing about their rhetoric is really hard for a bunch of interesting reasons. Since I didn’t get to write about it in the book, I’ll blather about it here. I still think rhetoric from groups like the Weathermen should be talked about more in our scholarship and teaching for several reasons. But it’s tough.

First, their writings, especially Prairie Fire (1974), are mind-numbing in a kind of interesting way (so this is a reason for and against writing about them). That may be a deliberate rhetorical choice. It might be what used to be called mystagoguery, in which the rhetoric is basically unintelligible, but it seems smart, and the fact that the audience can’t follow the argument is taken to mean that the author is sooo smart, a prophet with direct connection to the Truth that the audience doesn’t have (but might get by putting all their faith in the prophet). A lot of New Age self-help rhetoric works this way, as do most conspiracy theories.

The term mystagoguery quickly fell out of favor among scholars because the accusation of mystagoguery was so often just anti-intellectualism or an unconsidered hostility to specialist discourse. The problem was that people called something mystagoguery (especially literary theory) simply because they didn’t understand it. But something not making sense to a particular person doesn’t mean it’s unintelligible in general. Early Habermas made no sense to me for a long time because I didn’t understand the references, context, counter-arguments, and terms. Once I took the time to try to understand them, it made sense. I can’t follow an argument about super-string theory to save my life, but it isn’t mystagoguery—I’m just not in the audience. So, to argue that something is mystagoguery requires first engaging in the most charitable reading possible—trying to make sure one understands the references and so on–, and then explaining why, even in that context and so on the text doesn’t make sense.

Arguing that Prairie Fire is mystagoguery would require going deep into the specific kind of Maoist Marxist discourse of the Weathermen, and then either showing that it didn’t make sense, or that their use of it didn’t make sense. That’s a long slog I didn’t feel like making.

To claim something is mystagoguery is to attribute a fairly specific relationship between the rhetor and audience. The audience isn’t persuaded of the arguments made in the text, because the audience can’t even say exactly what those arguments are (let alone explain what many of the terms or phrases mean), but they can get a general gist (capitalism = bad; weathermen = good), and they believe that the rhetor does understand everything they are saying. So, the audience believes there is a very clear set of arguments and the rhetor is a genius who understands them.

In another kind of discourse, however, neither the rhetor nor audience believes that there is a set of comprehensible claims logically related to one another. The claims might be clear to the reader in isolation, but their relationship to one another is nonsense. Much Weatherman rhetoric, for instance, lists various ways that different groups are oppressed by American capitalism, and makes claims about what a revolution would do, and why now is the moment that various oppressed groups will see their shared oppression, rise up together, and overthrow capitalism in favor of a communist society. There isn’t any argumentation showing the connections among the claims, and those connections are vexed.

The notion that the white working class would, any minute now, realize that their interests were the same as BIPOC (all of whom have the same interests), environmentalists, prisoners, gays, Palestinians, women, and every other group mentioned in the pamphlet seems to me implausible. Although it was doctrine in some (not all) Marxist circles that the first step in revolution was a massive coalition of people who had realized their shared oppression, that wasn’t how any revolution had happened. But Prairie Fire, like a lot of demagoguery, argues through assertion, not argumentation. There are specifics and data, but the specific cases described function to exemplify the point being made, not as minor premises logically connected to a valid major premise.

In other words, there’s a different kind of rhetoric going on here, discourse that is fundamentally epideictic but with all the discursive surface markers of argumentation. It looks like argumentation, but it isn’t. That’s interesting.

Another aspect of Weathermen rhetoric that’s interesting for scholars and teachers of rhetoric is the question of effectiveness. At the time of Prairie Fire (1974), there were authors engaged in Marxist critiques of American education, carceral system, economy that, whether we agree with them or not, were engaged in argumentation, and they did change minds. People did read, for instance, Angela Davis on the prison system and change their mind about it. It’s hard to imagine that anyone would read Prairie Fire and have their mind changed about abolition, China, Palestine, the Rosenbergs, or the other sometimes apparently random topics discussed. But, the authors might not have been trying to persuade their audience about those issues.

Prairie Fire is a manifesto, and one of the major rhetorical functions of a manifesto is persuading an audience somewhat committed to the cause to become fully committed. Augustine famously said that a sermon might inform pagans about Christianity, persuade Christians to believe correct doctrine, and convince committed Christians to walk the walk (not his exact words). A manifesto tries to convince believers to become beleevers, largely by trying to persuade them that the group is fully committed to success, and will be effective because it’s in a tradition of successful social movements.

It doesn’t make that latter argument through a careful comparison of strategies, but by providing a geneaology in which Weather Underground is placed at the end of a narrative that includes Harriet Tubman, unions, Toussaint L’O[u]verture, and others whose precise relationship to the Weathermen is never clearly explained. But I think the implication that one is supposed to draw is associative, and not logical. And that’s interesting.

There’s one other point I want to make about effectiveness. It’s hard to find a good secondary on the Weathermen—some of the histories make them heroes and others villains, with very little in between. All the authors seem to have an axe to grind. The people who were involved in it are not necessarily motivated to be entirely honest about their reasons for joining the group. Still and all, there’s some indication that, at least for some people, it was the sex and drugs. So, did the verbal rhetoric even need to be plausible, let alone persuasive?

The main reason I really wanted to write about the rhetoric of Prairie Fire is that its rhetorical approach—accumulation, association, assertion, dismissal of any opposition or criticism through motivism—might be connected to the epistemological premises of a certain kind of Marxism that was popular in that era: a kind of enlightened and omniscient naïve realism.

Naïve realism says that the world is as it appears, and that, if we get back to direct perception (which is relatively easy for sensible people to do) then we will all see the same thing: the truth. Disagreement is necessarily a sign that someone is biased and their views should be dismissed.

There is also a kind of naïve realism that says that only some people (those who have been enlightened) can have that unmediated perception of the truth, and that their perception is universally valid—they are omniscient. This way of thinking about thinking is deeply anti-democratic, and yet common in democracies. It isn’t particular to democracies, nor is it specific to any one political affiliation.

There are four important assumptions involved in the enlightened and omniscient naïve realism model of identity and perception: 1) that there is a truth in any situation—a true way of thinking about religion, the truly best policy, a true narrative about a historical event; 2) a single individual can perceive this truth (that is, they can have a perspective-free, omniscient viewpoint, from which they can see everything that is true about poverty, the Trinity, WWI); 3) certain experiences (a particular kind of education, a conversion experience, success in business, military prowess) and/or group identity (wealthy, poor, GOP, Dem, white, young, old, so on) have either given them or signify their enlightened and omniscient naïve realism; 4) because their point of view is omniscient, everyone who disagrees with them is biased (by cupidity or stupidity), limited to one perspective (seeing only part of the situation), or lying (they know what the truth is, but it’s inconvenient, risky, or unpleasant, so they deliberately or choose the obviously wrong policy).

The political implications are pretty clear: there is one right policy solution to every problem. There is no such thing as intelligent and informed good faith disagreement. That one right solution is obvious to the right people, so disagreement is itself a reason to ban someone from the discussion, and to keep political power limited to the people who demonstrate enlightened omniscience. In other words, it’s anti-democratic. There may be forms and norms that appear democratic–the communist bloc nations had constitutions and Bills of Rights, and Massachusetts Bay Colony claimed to support “freedom of conscience.” But, in all those cases, people had the right to be right–that is, the right to agree and not the right to disagree.[1]

Ultimately, enlightened omniscient naive realism ends up in a tyranny of some form, perhaps a one-party state (such as Dinesh D’Souza advocates), a theocracy, herrrenvolk democracy, oligarchy, and so on.

In the case of the Weathermen, it ended up with their being racist, and that’s another interesting aspect of them. Because they were enlightened by virtue of their ideology, they saw themselves as better judges of the conditions of Black Americans than Black Americans, with the obvious consequence that they became notorious for whitesplaining. Their epistemology undermined their sincere attempts to be anti-racist.

Participating in politics is, as Hannah Arendt elegantly argued, a transcendental leap into uncertainty. We can reduce the uncertainty of any particular leap by using processes that reduce our reliance on cognitive biases, such as trying to find the smartest opposition arguments we can, trying to think about what evidence would cause us to change our mind, and making a distinction between agreeing with an argument and thinking it’s reasonable. Believing that there is only one right policy, and that we happen to know it is like making that leap without a rope, parachute, rescue plan, or map.



[1] When I make this argument, sometimes people think I’m arguing against vehemence, and I’m not. I think it’s great for people to be passionately committed to their argument. Being passionately committed to our argument, and arguing vehemently that someone else’s argument is wrong because their evidence is flawed, they’re missing important information, their sources are bad, and so on—that’s what democracy needs to be. Arguing that one’s preferred policy is the best is how people are likely to argue. But arguing that one’s preferred policy is the only possibility, and that every single other policy is obviously wrong, and obviously every single person who disagrees is a benighted, biased, corrupt, bigoted fool—that’s profoundly anti-democratic. Dismissing arguments because everyone not in the in-group has bad motives is the problem. It’s also false. None of us is actually the person who crawled out of Plato’s cave and sees the truth in every situation.





If you’re bragging that you aren’t “woke,” then you’re bragging that you’re racist

Theodore Bilbo


There are some things about people who call themselves “conservative” that I find really interesting. To be clear, I think conservatism, as advocated by Schlesinger, Niebuhr, Oakeshott, and various other theorists is an important view that we need in our political deliberations. I don’t agree with it or them—I think they’re wrong. But I think that political deliberation (or, to be honest, any policy deliberation) is better if there are people arguing from various premises (which, as I’ve said in many places, is not a binary or continuum of left v. right). We should have a public sphere of discourse in which there are people arguing vehemently for a social safety net, an unconstrained market, a market that is constrained in such a way to promote fair competition, isolationism, protective trade, free trade, a foreign policy that promotes our economic interests, a foreign policy that promotes democracy, a foreign policy, the government taking on issues of long-term concerns ignored by the market, and so many other positions.

And, if you think that range of positions is usefully represented by left v. right, then I would like to interest you in some shares in the Brooklyn Bridge. Just think about what you could make with the tolls.

The media is demagogic to keep referring to sources or figures as “conservative” who simply aren’t. Fox News isn’t conservative—it’s pro-GOP. And the GOP is rarely conservative.

Conservatism is skepticism about social change, grounded in skepticism about human nature (so “prosperity gospel” is completely incompatible with conservatism). In fact, people who call themselves “conservative” are far closer to “neo-liberal” than “conservative,” at least insofar as what they claim to have as principles. Neo-liberals (such as Reagan) endorse “a policy model that encompasses both politics and economics and seeks to transfer the control of economic factors from the public sector to the private sector. Many neoliberalism policies enhance the workings of free market capitalism and attempt to place limits on government spending, government regulation, and public ownership.”

The GOP is and has long been intermittently neo-liberal; they’re neo-liberal in terms of the principles they claim to have, but not in terms of policy agenda, as various sources have noted. The one position on which the GOP has been consistent since 1968 is racism—sometimes dog whistle, and sometimes trumpeted. When it comes to neo-Jim Crow policies (that is, laws that make it harder for non-whites to vote) they reject the notion that a free market will lead to the right outcomes. And they long have–the Georgia race-based voter suppression “is the sort of policy Republicans used to enact quietly, with little protest, back before everybody detested them.”

So, in the GOP ideological world, saying that someone is “woke” is an insult. What does it mean to be “woke”?

I have to say that I haven’t heard a leftist use the term “woke” in anything other than an ironic way in years, but a google search suggests that some people are still using it in the old way, which was “being awake to social injustices , especially those created by racist institutions.”

What’s incredibly weird about how the pro-GOP media and supporters use the term is that’s what they mean too. They believe that being “woke” means calling attention to racist injustice.

They think it’s a joke because because they believe that there is no racism. Because they’re racist.

Although they admit that non-whites have higher rates of getting arrested, convicted, and killed, have a harder time getting jobs or apartments, and are generally treated worse, they think that’s because non-whites deserve the treatment they get—a very racist belief. Pro-GOP are sad puppies because racist books don’t win prizes, publishers decide not to publish racist books, scholars who do shitty research that supports racism have trouble getting published, people who say racist things get criticized, racists get fired, companies and advertisers don’t want to be associated with racists. They’re victims because they can’t advocate racism without getting called racist.

So, people who claim to be the party that advocates personal responsibility feel sorry for themselves if people hold them responsible for their statements and actions. If you’re bragging that you aren’t “woke,” you’re bragging that you’re racist, and you’re bragging that you’re a whiner who doesn’t like to be called racist.



Grammar Nazis and deflected/projected racism

marked up draft

My mother, who was very racist but sincerely believed herself to be not racist, said that she was not personally opposed to intermarriage, but she was opposed to it, on the grounds that it was so hard on the children. In other words, she supported a racist practice (social shaming of “intermarriage”) while still feeling herself not racist because she could tell herself that her racist practice was necessitated by the racism of other people.

Teachers—all teachers, at every level—are far too often my mother. We teach in a racist way, all the while claiming that we, personally, aren’t racist, but our racist practice is necessary because of the racism of others. We do it when it comes to teaching “standard Edited American English” (a particular dialect) as though it is better than other dialects.

English has a lot of different dialects, and many of those dialects are grammatically different. Standard Edited American English (SEAE), for instance (a dialect no one speaks), prohibits the comma splice (The cats ran, the dogs barked), but Standard Edited British English doesn’t. In spoken English, sentence fragments are fine, and are also fine in much published writing (depending on formality), but generally prohibited in very formal writing (except resumes or cv, where they are required). It would be inappropriate for someone to use full sentences in a resume, and therefore equally inappropriate for someone to mark a resume as “wrong” for using sentence fragments. Sentence fragments aren’t therefore “worse” than complete sentences–they’re appropriate or not; that’s how language works.

However, in any language there are dialects that are stigmatized for racist, classist, historical, or various other bigoted reasons. They’re stigmatized as “bad” English (or French, or German, or whatever). In American English, one use of the double negative is stigmatized and the other accepted because one is associated with Black English. “She don’t know nuthin’ about nuthin’” is a perfectly clear sentence, but “The argument is not unclear” takes math to understand. Yet, it’s the first that gets called “bad English.” (Which is funny, if you think about it–calling something “bad English” is itself an instance of using the wrong term, so it’s “worse” English than a double negative.)

So, it’s important to separate out two kinds of grammatical errors: a violation of a dialect from within that dialect (such as someone trying to write SEAE who violates rules of that dialect, such as the muddled Black English of The Help), ones that are correct usage within that dialect but not accepted in the dialect a reader is expecting. (A third category would be uses of language that aren’t grammatically incorrect at all, but people think they are–ending a sentence with a preposition, for instance.)

Here’s what I mean by the second kind of error. It would be bizarre for someone to chastise someone speaking German for ending a sentence with a preposition—that’s how German works. (It’s also how English works, but that’s a different post.) It would also be sheer bigotry to say that French is better than German because French doesn’t allow ending sentences with prepositions. Dialects and languages are all equally good at communicating; none is better than another.

I’ll mention something about the first toward the end of this post, but, for the most part, I want to focus on what we do about stigmatized dialects. The problem is that, since, for instance, Black English is stigmatized, and Standard Edited American English is rewarded, should teachers require that their students learn Standard Edited American English?

The advice for years (ever since the National Council of Teachers of English and Conference on College Composition and Communication issued the Statement on Students’ Right to Their Own Language”) has been to advocate code-switching. To say that a student should know SEAE because it’s useful, not because it’s better, is like saying that it’s useful to know French if you intend to live and work in France. From within this model, German is no better than French (nor is French better than German), and a student might be speaking perfect German in a French class. A person shouldn’t give up German, but add on the knowledge of French. Students should learn SEAE as an additional dialect that is useful under some circumstances.[1]

Unfortunately, too many teachers and professors and employers and people in power use the language of code-switching in order to enforce the message that Black English is inferior.

A few years ago I found myself in an argument on the internet with a white teacher in a predominantly African American school who banned Black English in her classes. She was proud that she told her students that Black English would hold them back. She wasn’t racist, she insisted; she was helping them. There’s what might seem like a subtle difference between what she was doing and what “Students’ Right to Their Own Language” advocates, but it’s an important one. She was clear that SEAE was better than Black English, that Black English was something they should be shamed for using. I then noticed that I often had the same problem with training people in the teaching of writing—they made a bigger deal about perfectly clear uses of stigmatized language than they did about about grammar problems that interfered with communication. They did so, they said, because other people would be racist.

It’s my mother opposing “intermarriage” because other people would be racist. That’s racist.

Granted, we’re in a racist world, and using a stigmatized dialect will hurt a person in terms of job or housing applications, getting good scores on standardized tests, or dealing with racist teachers who deflect their racism onto others who might be racist. So, I understand, and still support, the idea that we should teach code-switching, but if (and only if) we give students the ability to choose whether they want to learn to code-switch, we do so by making it absolutely clear that no dialect is better than another, and we make a bigger deal about violations of grammar and usage within (rather than across) dialects. I don’t know that we can do the second, and if that’s the case, then teaching code-switching is racist.

I mentioned that violations within a dialect are worth looking at carefully, largely because they can signal issues with thinking. For instance, mixing metaphors can indicate that we haven’t decided on the underlying model, or that we’re appealing to troubling models, or that we just aren’t thinking. I once heard a facilitator say, “We’re on a fast train flying out of the box.” She was describing a train wreck, as far as I could tell, but I think she meant it as a good thing. I don’t know. Had she said, “We ain’t done nothin’ about nothin’” I could have understood her perfectly.

Unclear pronoun reference can mean we haven’t really decided how causality works. For instance, if I say, “There are bunnies eating kale in the backyard, which is weird,” it isn’t clear whether the weird part is that there are bunnies, that they’re eating kale, that they’re doing it in the backyard.” In other words, it isn’t clear what “which” is referring to. What’s interesting to me about these sorts of errors (predication error or mixed construction is another one along these lines) is that “correcting” the error means first figuring out what I’m trying to say. These are interesting and significant errors.

Whenever I get into this topic (or when it comes up even on scholarly mailing lists), people advocating my position (the position of most if not all linguists, btw) get accused of thinking that anything goes, and that we shouldn’t care about clarity or correctness of any kind. That isn’t what I’m saying. I’m making four points. First, no dialect is better than any other (it might be more useful, inappropriate, effective under certain circumstances). Second, what grammar Nazis worry about are often not “grammar” issues at all (but style preferences, hypercorrectness, misunderstandings of rules, misapplications of rules), and are almost always not issues of clarity, but are class or race markers (e.g., comma splices, double negatives, subject-verb agreement, ending with a preposition). Third, we should worry about certain issues of usage, but it should be the ones that are violations within a dialect, especially ones that signal muddled thinking. Fourth, the conventional wisdom among experts for years has been that we should teach code-switching (that is, the ability to switch between dialects), but that’s still racist unless we do so in a way that makes it clear that we aren’t privileging one dialect over another, and we offer it as a choice to students.


[1] Another way to put this is to say that prescriptivism is perfectly fine, as long as it’s taught qua prescriptivism.

Racism, Biden, Trump, and the bad math of whaddaboutism

boxes

John Stoehr has a nice piece about what he calls the “malicious nihilism” of Trump supporting media and pundits. They’ve stopped trying to argue that Trump is not racist, since he explicitly stokes racism, but, they’re saying, since Biden is a Democrat, and Democrats used to be the party of racists, then Biden is racist too: “Fine, the GOP partisans now say, Trump is a racist. The Democrats are just as bad, though. May as well vote for the Republican.”

That’s just plain bad math.

It’s easy to point to so many things Trump and his Administration has said and done that are racist. Critics of Biden point to one thing he said, and what the Democratic Party was like prior to 1970. Those are not comparable. That way of thinking about Biden v. Trump ignores the important questions of degrees, impact, persistence.

It’s a weirdly common way of arguing about politics, though, and even interpersonal issues. There was a narrative about the Civil War for a long time which was that “both sides were just as bad,” and it was the mutual extremism about the issue of slavery that led to war.[1] The “mutual extremism” was this same bad math. There was one President between John Adams and Abraham Lincoln who didn’t own slaves (JQ Adams), Congress was so proslavery that the House and Senate both banned criticism of slavery for years (the gag rules), the Supreme Court ruled that African Americans could never be citizens. Criticism of slavery in slaver states could be punished by hanging; the Fugitive Slave Laws enabled slavers to kidnap African Americans in “free” states. Pro-slavery rhetoric regularly called for race war should abolition happen, and began calling for secession to protect slavery in the 1820s. Commitment to slavery was so dominant in slaver states that they went to war against the US.

There were pro-slavery Presidents; there was no abolitionist President (JQAdams would, after his presidency, become anti-slavery, but not clearly abolitionist). No state had a death penalty for advocating slavery; there was no gag rule for advocating slavery; abolitionists didn’t advocate civil war or race war; no one could go into a slaver state and declare an African American to be free and face the same low bar that kidnappers in the “free” states faced.

They weren’t both “just as bad” because they didn’t equally advocate violence, they weren’t equally powerful, advocating civil war was commonplace on only one side, the laws and practices they advocated weren’t equally extreme.

I wrote a book about proslavery rhetoric, and when I would make this point—“both sides” weren’t “just as bad”—neo-Confederates would say, “What about John Brown?” That’s the bad math. If, on one side, advocating and engaging in violence is commonplace, then one example on the other side doesn’t mean they’re both just as bad. You can even bring in Bloody Kansas and not get the amount of violence (and advocacy of violence) commonplace in supporting slavery to be anything close to the violence on the part of critics of slavery.

Here is my crank theory about why people reason that way. A lot of people really don’t (perhaps can’t) think in terms of degrees. They think in terms of categories (this is not the crank theory party—it’s a fairly common observation). Thus, you’re racist or not, certain or clueless, proud or ashamed; something is good or bad, right or wrong, correct or incorrect; you’re in-group or out-group, loyal or disloyal. They don’t think about degrees of racism, certainty, pride, goodness, loyalty, and so on.

There’s a funny paradox. Because they don’t think in terms of degrees (or mixtures—something might be loyal in some ways and disloyal in others), they believe that you either have a rigid, black/white ethical system, or you’re what they call a “moral relativist.” They actually mean “nihilist.” So, they hear “right v. wrong might be a question of degrees rather than absolutes” as saying there is no difference between right and wrong—one of their crucial binaries is “rigid ethical system of categories or nihilism.” That binary imbues those other binaries with ethical value—being rigid about loyalty v. disloyalty seems to be part of being a “good” person.

Because people like this think in terms of putting things in a box—something goes in the box of good or bad, racist or not racist, loyal or disloyal, then, if they can find a single racist thing related to Biden, he and Trump are in the same box. And, therefore, that box can be ignored when it comes to comparing them, since they’re both in it.

And this brings us back to Stoehr’s point. The attachment to rigidity, the tendency to think in terms of absolutes and not degrees makes these people actually incapable of ethical decision-making. Since wildly different actions are thrown into the box of “bad” or “racist,” people who reason this way can’t tell right from wrong. They can end up allowing, tolerating, encouraging, or even actively supporting wildly unethical actions because of their inability to think in nuanced ways about ethics. It’s moral nihilism.




[1] There weren’t only two sides, so the claim that “both sides” were anything is nonsensical. There were, at least, six sides. Pro-slavery/pro-secession, pro-slavery/anti-secession, anti-slavery/pro-colonization, anti-slavery/pro-full citizenship, anti-anti-slavery, anti-pro-slavery.

Are Trump supporters racist? Yes. Are Biden supporters racist? Yes. Are they equally racist? No.

Notice that Japanese Americans must report for internment

Far too many people (mostly white)….

…..think that I just did something racist by saying “mostly white.”

People might think that because, if you stop someone on the street and ask them, “what does it mean to be racist?,” a lot of them would say it means:

1) consciously categorizing people by race;

2) and you can know that someone is doing that by “making race an issue” (that is, mentioning race);

3) “stereotyping” a race (that is, making a generalization about it), especially if the generalization is negative;

4) as a consequence of that conscious negative stereotype about the race, treating everyone of that race with aggression and hostility.

It would seem I’ve violated the first through third rule, so, if you think those are good ways of deciding what racism is, I’m racist.

Those actually aren’t good ways of deciding that something is racist (although it’s true that I’m racist). In the first place, these rules imply useless and cognitively impossible solutions to racism. They suggest that the solution to racism is to: not see race; not mention race; not make generalizations about groups; and never consciously behave badly to someone just because of their race.

In the US, we can’t not see race. Race is so important in our culture that saying you don’t see race is like saying you don’t see gender. Unless you are literally blind, you see race and gender. Those are the things we notice about someone immediately. We’re often wrong about someone’s gender, just as we’re often wrong about someone’s “race,” but we can’t help but categorize people. Individuals can resist, but never completely free ourselves of, the culture in which we have been raised. Even Gandhi struggled to free himself of thinking in terms of the caste system. What matters about Gandhi is that he recognized, and acknowledged (publicly) that he wasn’t free of thinking about people from within the caste system, and he tried to account for it.

Aristotle describes ethical action as much like aiming with a bow and arrow. His argument was that every virtue has extremes on either side. It’s a vice to be reckless, and a vice to be cowardly. It’s a vice to be spendthrift, and a vice to be a miser. We all have a tendency toward one extreme or another, just as we are prone to pull to one side or another when aiming a bow and arrow. [1] We need to acknowledge our tendency, so that we can adjust for it. That’s how racism works. We can’t escape it, but we can try to figure out how much it’s making us miss the mark, and adjust for it.

Aristotle’s point is that none of us is born with perfect aim. We can get to ethical actions by acknowledging our tendency to unethical action. The notion that acknowledging (or naming) race makes the action/statement racist guarantees we will not correct our aim. It’s like saying that your shot must have been good because you don’t see misses.

So, are Trump supporters racist? Yes. Are Biden supporters? Yes. They/we are all racist because we’re all Americans and Americans are racist. But not equally so.

Racism isn’t an either/or. It isn’t that we’re racist or not; it’s how racist we are and what we’re doing about it. It’s the fourth (false) criterion for racism that enables racism most effectively.

Racism is an unconscious bias. No one is unbiased. That isn’t how cognition works. You can’t perceive the world without perceiving it in light of what you already believe. Imagine that you’re a white person trying to find an office in a university building. You can find the door to the building because you have a stereotype about how buildings work. You walk past classrooms because you have a stereotype about classrooms. You walk into a room because you have a stereotype (and prejudices) about what an office looks like. For instance, it might say on the door, “Department of Rhetoric,” and you’re looking for that department. You have a prejudice (you have prejudged) that departments put their name on a door.

That’s why the argument that you shouldn’t stereotype groups is nonsense. We stereotype. That’s how we think. The very statement, “Generalizations are bad” is a generalization. Generalizing isn’t the problem.

You walk in to that office. There are several people. Whom do you assume is the executive assistant, and whom do you assume is the Department Chair?

You see a tall white male with slightly graying hair, a short stout Black woman of the same age as the white male, a younger white woman elegantly dressed, a person whose race and gender you can’t immediately identify. Whom do you treat as the receptionist?

Your decisions about whom to treat as the Chair are just as much questions of prejudging, stereotypes, and expectations as your decisions regarding finding the door (and it’s decisions, and not decision—there are a lot of factors). You can rely on your prejudgments, stereotypes, and expectations, or you can decide to treat humans differently from doors. You can’t not have the prejudgments; you can treat know that you have prejudgments and then act differently.

Racism isn’t getting up in the morning and deciding on whose lawn you’ll burn a cross. Racism is assuming the Black woman isn’t the Chair.

Does that mean that the non-racist thing to do is to walk into the office groveling in shame, filled with guilt, hating your whiteness? If you get your information from the GOP-propaganda machine, that’s what you’d think. They say that being anti-racist means being ashamed of being white (something no anti-racist activist has ever said would solve racism). Would walking into that room full of shame for being white change anything about the interaction? If, full of shame, you assumed the white guy was the chair, you’re still racist.

A lot of people assume that racism is a sin of commission, and the common notion about sins of commission is that you know you’re doing something that is a sin and you do it anyway. I think that’s pretty rare in racism. In fact, I’m not sure it’s ever the case.

My experience is that racists—even actual Nazis—don’t (or didn’t) see themselves as acting out of racism. Nazis these days call themselves “racial realists,” the real Nazis claimed that they were acting on the basis of objective and realist science. Racists think racism is irrational hostility to a race; racists believe that their stereotypes are grounded in data.

They’re grounded in confirmation bias.

Sometimes, racists say that they aren’t racist because their actions–such as wanting to restrict immigration from some group–are grounded in concerns about politics, not race. Therefore, they aren’t racist!

That’s how race-based genocide is justified. Native Americans had to be exterminated because they were a military threat. Jews were, the Nazis said, a political threat, as were Poles, Czechs, and various other non-Aryan “races” of central and eastern Europe. The people who engaged in lynching didn’t say they were doing something racist; they said they were trying to preserve a social order (that was racist). I’ve spent a lot of time crawling around the nastiest of the nastiest racist writings—both current and historical—and I can’t think of a time when racists called what they were doing “racist.”

In other words, even people engaged in racist-based genocide—the most extreme version of racism–have ways of rationalizing those actions so that they don’t see themselves as committing the sin of racism. Racism never seems to the racist to be a sin of commission because there are ways of pretending it isn’t racism–we pretend it’s about upholding “objective” (actually racist) standards (such as standardized tests, or arrest rates), reducing crime (but really the crime of not being white).

These were exactly the ways that Nazis criminalized being Jewish. Jews were more criminal, they said, and had arrest rates to prove it (because Jews were arrested for things that wouldn’t have resulted in an arrest for non-Jews), science that agreed Jews were essentially criminal, and media that promoted the stereotype of Jews as criminal.

Are Trump supporters racist? Yes, because they support the most openly racist President we’ve had since Wilson. Racism isn’t a binary; it’s a continuum. And Trump is very far on the racist side of the continuum.

Are Biden supporters racist? Yes, because Americans are racist. He isn’t as racist as Trump.

Does it hurt the feelings of Trump supporters to be called racist? Well, then don’t be racist. One way for Trump supporters to show they aren’t racist is for them to condemn Trump’s racism. Until they do, they’re more racist than Biden supporters.

If I’m a shitty driver and regularly run people over, I don’t get to say that I’m just as hurt by being called a shitty driver as the people are hurt by my running them over. If I want to stop being called a shitty driver, I should try to learn to drive better.


[1] If you’re a geek about this kind of thing, and you want a very scholarly, but beautifully written, book about the Athenians of Aristotle’s era and justice, Martha Nussbaum’s Fragility of Goodness changed my world.









Confusing conversations about police violence

Five men falsely accused and imprisoned
Image from https://www.history.com/topics/1980s/central-park-five

When the videos came out of Rodney King getting assaulted, I found myself in a conversation with a Libertarian (call her Emma Libertarian) who said something along the lines of “What the police did was justified because he was driving drunk.”

I don’t exactly remember what I said, but I think I tried to point out that a beating is not the punishment for drunk driving, that King hadn’t even been convicted yet, so shouldn’t be punished, and that beating would be cruel and unusual punishment. What Emma was advocating would violate the Bill of Rights at least twice. To me, that seemed the opposite of Libertarianism.

I misunderstood Emma’s commitment to Libertarianism.

There’s another conversation in which I’ve found myself so often that I’m not even sure I can pick a specific episode (call the interlocutor Hubert Lawandorder). The police officer does something illegal—in other words, commits a crime—and the victim of the crime refuses to go along with it. And so the officer escalates the situation, and the person who objected to a crime being committed ends up arrested or perhaps dead.

So, for instance, an individual gets the attention of a police officer. An officer insists that the person leave their house, submit to a warrantless search of themselves or their home, not have a gun, confess to a crime, not ask what the charge is. What’s confusing about this conversation with Hubert Lawandorder—which I have had far too many times—is that Hubert agrees with me that the officer is violating the rights of the accused, and even violating very specific laws and regulations. We agree that the officer is breaking the law. But Hubert, who sees himself as a believer in Law and Order, not only believes that the police don’t have to follow the law they are supposed to be enforcing, but that the officer is justified in arresting anyone who objects to the police officer’s illegal activity, and that the officer is justified in escalating the interaction.

Hubert, like Emma Libertarian, believes in police vigilantism. To me, that seemed the opposite of supporting Law and Order.

I misunderstood Hubert’s commitment to Law and Order.

There are lots of ways of explaining why they don’t see their position as contradictory, and I kept thinking that with Emma it had to do with varieties of Libertarianism, and with Hubert it was something about a higher Law. I misunderstood that too.

I realized that I’d misunderstood why they didn’t see their positions as problematic when disagreeing with a Hubert Lawandorder, and I finally asked the question with which I should have started every one of those conversations: “So, if a police officer asked to search your house without a warrant, you’d say yes?”

[I’d sometimes asked, “If a police officer handcuffed you just because you asked why you were pulled over, would you be okay with that?” And Hubert would say, “I’m always polite and deferential to officers, so that would never happen to me.” That response meant we ended up in a weird argument as to whether the victim of police abuse had been polite.]

But the warrant question got a different response. Hubert would say, “No, I wouldn’t let the police search my house without a warrant.”

And, then, quite often, Hubert would say, “But I would never give the police reason to suspect me.” So, it wasn’t about a principle of searching with or without a warrant—it was about a failure of imagination.

It was at that moment that I realized that, while both Emma Libertarian and Hubert Lawandorder talked a lot about principles (people should respect the constitution, people should respect the law), that talk had as much relation to their thinking as the word “quality” (in quotes) in a business logo has to the quality of the products. It’s just a sales pitch.

Were those actual principles, they would apply across groups, and they didn’t. Emma Libertarian wouldn’t think it okay if the police pulled her out of a car and beat her just because they thought she disrespected them. Hubert Lawandorder wouldn’t say “Well, okay,” to a no-knock warrant that meant people who might not have identified themselves as police crash into his house at night with weapons drawn. It isn’t that they thought police vigilantism was always right—it’s that they couldn’t imagine it happening to them. They imagined themselves as people protected, rather than endangered, by vigilante police not beholden to the law.

They did so because of what’s called the “just world model.” The “just world model” says that, if something bad happens to you, it’s because you did something to deserve that outcome. The just world model is attractive for two reasons. First, like all magical thinking (if you do this, that will definitely happen), it takes a world of inexplicable outcomes, a world we can’t actually control, and draws it into our control. It enables Emma to believe that something like police violence won’t happen to her because of what she does. [1]

Second, and closely related to the first, it says that we aren’t called to help the marginalized—the poor, ill, elderly, the victims of racism–, nor are we facing systemic injustice. The just world model is radically individual (which is why it’s so closely associated with neoliberalism). If you fail in life (or get cancer, or get shot by the police), it wasn’t because of larger issues of poverty, pollution, racism, or a police force indoctrinated to see itself as an army of occupation.[2] The just world model says we earned what we have, and are entitled to keep all of it.

The just world model is racist.

It may seem weird to say that it’s racist, since it doesn’t say anything about race, and neither Emma nor Hubert said anything about race. But racism isn’t necessarily about what you’re aware of believing—it’s often (most often?) about what you’re able to avoid thinking, seeing, or imagining.

Since racism is a “hot cognition” issue, it might be helpful to talk about the just world model in regard to something not about race. The just world model says that people who are financially successful did something to deserve it, so they must have good judgment. It’s interesting to think about the number of CEO who were praised as geniuses just before they were exposed as frauds (such as Elizabeth Holmes, Kenneth Lay, or Adam Neumann). It’s a scam going all the way back to the Segestans (who conned the Athenians)—if you look wealthy, people will think you are.

They’re often successful in that scam for quite a while. So, were those con artists good people whom you should trust because they were rewarded with wealth? The just world model says they are. The just world model says you should have given all your money to Bernie Madoff, Elizabeth Holmes, Kenneth Lay.

The just world model gets you scammed.

And it does so by triggering an aspect of confirmation bias that enables deflection of uncomfortable information. That was a complicated sentence. Here’s what I mean. We are primed (biased) to notice information that confirms what we believe. Let’s imagine that I believe that people who own poodles are snobby jerks, and I love Great Danes. I am likely to notice every instance of a poodle owner being a jerk. More important, I’m likely to interpret ambiguous data (a fight between a poodle and Great Dane) as the poodle being at fault. If it isn’t ambiguous (the Great Dane attacked the poodle), all of my first impulses will be to blame the poodle—it provoked the Dane; it deserved it. That is the just world model.

What’s funny about people who believe in the just world model is that, when they find themselves on the wrong side of policies or decisions, they whine like an over-tired toddler. Where is your just world now?

The just world model is a complete failure of empathy. And that’s why it’s racist.

A white person saying that anyone who gets shot by the police deserved it is unintentionally acknowledging that we have a system in which white people are protected. Because they’re admitting they don’t think it can happen to us. All those white people confronting POC in parks, pools, sidewalks of their own homes—that wouldn’t happen to me. Not because I’m polite. But because I’m white.

If you, as a white person, have any POC in your world (if you actually “have a black friend”) then you have heard them describe experiences with the police you have never had. If you have never heard (or listened to, or read about) those experiences, then you’re racist. Not because you act with feelings of aggression, but because of your failure of imagination. You never listened.

If, having heard that POC behave just as you do, and yet they get hassled, harassed, or even arrested by the police, and you still blame them for what happened, you’re racist. You’re also an asshole.

If a POC individual can behave as well as a white individual, and get shot or arrested, then policing is racist.

And here is the other point. If police officers can’t enforce the law without thereby making themselves someone who should be arrested for violating the law, then there is something very wrong with the system. We need a different system.

The argument that the police shouldn’t be held to the law is an admission that it’s a broken system—it isn’t about a few bad apples.

When pushed on this point—that they don’t imagine themselves on the wrong side of a vigilante police officer who will violate the law in order to arrest them–, people with whom I’m arguing sometimes show what’s really at stake. Some of them say that it’s okay for the police to treat white people differently from African Americans because African Americans are more criminal. (This claim is often premised by “I’m not racist, but it’s a fact that…”) They say that the African-American community (that isn’t always the term they use) glorifies criminality, promiscuity, drug use. Their evidence for this stereotype about the African-American community is what their media tells them about rap music. (I’m not kidding—that’s what they cite as evidence to me. Sometimes they cite Ben Carson saying the black community is bad. They used to cite Bill Cosby, but they don’t anymore.)

Emma and Hubert are racist. They might never have said the ‘n’ word; they might even give to “liberal” causes; they might have a relative or friend who is POC. But if they refuse to see that policing is racist, it’s because they’ve got blinkered loyalty. And it’s blinkered to keep them from acknowledging racism.

Ian Kershaw, a scholar of the Holocaust, famously said that “The road to Auschwitz was built with hate, but it was paved with indifference.” I would put that somewhat more strongly. It was paved by people willing to rationalize the injustice. Emma and Hubert are busily engaged in paving a road.






[1] Self-help rhetoric does this a lot. (“The three tricks that successful investors have…” or CrossFit). I should say that I, personally, have found a lot of self-help rhetoric tremendously helpful. When it gets into reinforcing the just world model is when it makes claims about “all you have to do is” or this method “guarantees” an outcome. Anytime it says that success is guaranteed if you have sufficient commitment or will, it’s toxic, and quite possibly a scam.

[2] The just world model simultaneously reinforces privilege (of class, race, ableism, gender) and denies its existence. But that’s a different post.

White people feeling bad is not the solution to police violence

George Wallace

The events of the last few days make it clear that racism is not about how individuals feel about each other. It’s about how structures and systemic practices fuel our racist system—everything from how cop shows narrate events to the history of Supreme Court rulings on qualified immunity. Our system is racist in a lot of ways, and one of them is that it privileges the feelings of white people. (That’s why Trump is the whitest of Presidents—everything is about his feelings.)

So, if you’re a white person interested in helping make our world less racist, then writing about how badly we feel about what’s happening is still doing the thing. Racism isn’t about how white people feel bad. Racism won’t be ended when white people feel more bad, or more white people feel bad, or, whatever. Racism isn’t about individual white people having individual white people feelings.

Racism is about white people feelings driving the world. So, white people treating our current situation as though the solution is white people telling POC how we feel is still saying that white people fee-fees are the most important thing right now. Making racialized and unaccountable policing about white people fee-fees is doubling down on the racism. Just don’t. It’s about the policing, not our feelings.

It also doesn’t help if white people turn to our “black friend” and say that we are now willing to listen to them. Our “black friend” is not our spiritual guide. S/he might have other things to do, and we have google.

There are some great lists out there of really helpful books to read. Here is Ibram X. Kendi‘s .

Here’s one that includes Kendi’s work.

This is a list specifically for white people.








Racism, Motivism, and Disparate Impact

George Wallace

One of the reasons people often don’t try to talk about racism, especially persistent (but kind of low-key) racism, is that the conversations go so badly. And they go badly for two reasons I want to mention here (there are others).

First, it’s that the racism is low-key. By “low-key,” I don’t mean it’s innocuous, or not a big problem. I mean that the racist acts don’t necessarily fit conventional notions of what racists do: there might be a complete absence of racist epithets, an avoidance of even mentioning race, and the people engaged in racism might not be consciously trying to be what they think of as racist. Sometimes it’s done through unconscious passive-aggressive actions and comments, or even behavior that the person thinks is anti-racist (such as endorsing the deficit model of culture). There can be a conscious intent to be “fair,” “objective,” “have high standards” and so on, without the thought “Oh, boy oh boy, how can I make this decision in the most racist way possible?” And it’s persistent. It’s low-key like a low-key note that is playing constantly, that is part of every decision, and therefore tremendously harmful, but it is so constant that people don’t even notice it.

Because it’s constant, it seems normal, and so people can’t see it as racist. And, if you try to name it as racist, they’ll argue it isn’t because it isn’t the open hostility racist epithet kind of racism. Because they can imagine a worse racism, they deflect the criticism that what they’re doing (or enabling) is racist. It’s like saying that because I only robbed one bank, and I know of people who’ve robbed ten, I’m not really a bank robber.

That deflection of racism is the consequence of seeing racism as SO evil that normal people couldn’t possibly engage in it. There’s another odd quality that is the consequence of framing racism as something extreme—the assumption that it must always be at play (leading to the “some of my best friends are X” or “I get along great with this person who is X”). There are some interesting studies from years ago in which people watched videos of a doctor interacting with patients. If the doctor was ethnically out-group and the patient was ethnically in-group, and the interaction went well, then the test subjects (the ones watching the video) were unlikely to mention race. But, if things went badly, the watchers attributed the doctor’s bad behavior to race.

Racism isn’t a feeling; it’s an explanation.

And it’s almost always an explanation about motive. The reason that many white people on public assistance have no problem condemning POC on public assistance as “lazy” and advocating a reduction in the social safety net is that they don’t see themselves as scamming the system—they need the assistance but “those people” don’t. It’s the same behavior (being on public assistance) but judged differently because of the assumption of different motives—the in-group has good motives and the out-group has bad motives.

That’s typical of in-group/out-group explanations, but, when it comes to race, there are tragic consequences. White people on juries are likely to empathize with white defendants and be persuaded by arguments about extenuating circumstances, when they would assume bad motives on the part of POC defendants. And this is all unconscious.

How most people think about racism is so odd—in addition to assuming it has to be conscious, people often assume that it has some weird kind of monocausal quality. So, for instance, if your treatment of me can be shown to have been affected by anything other than racism, then it wasn’t racism. This is the “He isn’t racist, he’s just a jerk” argument. And he may be a jerk, but there’s nothing that keeps someone from being both a jerk and racist.

But, if a person is a jerk to a lot of people, and is a jerk to POC, many people are unlikely to call that bad behavior toward POC racist (“he’s just a jerk”). And they’ll argue it isn’t really racist without looking to see whether there is some kind of difference (it’s more frequent, harsher, has bigger consequences when POC are the object of jerk behavior). It’s a missing stair situation.

The Pervocracy describes a missing stair as:

Have you ever been in a house that had something just egregiously wrong with it?  Something massively unsafe and uncomfortable and against code, but everyone in the house had been there a long time and was used to it?  “Oh yeah, I almost forgot to tell you, there’s a missing step on the unlit staircase with no railings.  But it’s okay because we all just remember to jump over it.”

Some people are like that missing stair. [….] Just about every workplace has that one person who doesn’t do their job, but everyone’s grown accustomed to picking up their slack. A lot of social groups and families have that one person. The person whose tip you quietly add a couple bucks to. (Maybe more than a couple, after how they talked to the server.) The person you don’t bother arguing with when they get off on one of their rants. The person you try really, really hard not to make angry, because they’re perfectly nice so long as no one makes them angry.

The problem is that vulnerable people are more likely to have trouble avoiding the missing stair, and are more likely to get injured. The missing stair affects POC disparately.

It doesn’t matter if the jerk means to treat POC differently; intent doesn’t matter. Even if the jerk was equally a jerk to everyone, if there are greater consequences, regardless of intent, for POC, then it’s disparate impact. And that’s discrimination.

And it’s racist. And it’s racist for someone not to try to stop the jerk from being a jerk if their jerkiness has a disparate impact on POC.

I’m white and argumentative af, privileged, and very hard to intimidate, and even I have given up trying to talk to some people about racism because they are so committed to deflecting the issue to anything other than racism, especially anything other than systemic racism. And if I find it exhausting, then how many other people who are less privileged, less argumentative, and more vulnerable have also given up?

Racism isn’t about feelings

Notice that Japanese Americans must report for internment

If you stop someone on the street and ask them, “What does it mean to be racist? And what’s wrong with racism?” you’d probably get an answer something along the lines of, “Racism is a feeling of hostility that some individuals have toward members of other races, and it’s harmful because, when they express that hostility, it hurts the feelings of others.” (Or perhaps, “It offends other people.”) In other words, racism is about individuals having feelings that are likely to create bad feelings in other individuals.

It’s one of the least useful, and most damaging, ways of thinking about racism and what it does.

For instance, it flattens various actions, as though they’re the same—if racism is about hurt feelings, then my feeling hurt that you called me racist seems just as important as your feeling hurt that I said something racist.

It also prohibits third parties from being able to call out racism (or mischaracterizes their objecting to racism as “being offended”–still about their feelings). If racism is a problem because it hurts the feelings of members of the race who’ve been “insulted,” then no third party has the right to say, “Hey, what you said was racist.” After all, they weren’t insulted, so their feelings weren’t hurt. There was no harm.

I have a friend whose mother is from Mexico, and my friend self-identifies as bi-racial Latina, but she doesn’t fit the physical stereotype that racists tend to have about Latinas, and so she has often found herself in a group of people where someone says something racist about “Mexicans.” If she objects to the racism without revealing that they’re insulting her, then she gets called “politically correct” and they double down on their racist claim, saying something like, “Well, you know it’s true.”

If she reveals that she’s in the group they’re attacking, then they apologize. But they don’t apologize for thinking the racist thing, or for saying it, but for saying it in front of her.

Each of those responses—refusing to listen to someone objecting to racism on the grounds that person is just being “politically correct” and apologizing, not for being racist, but for being racist in front of her– seems like a reasonable response to them because, having been taught that racism is harmful because it hurts the feelings of people of that race, it would seem that a person not of that race has no real reason to object, and their only injury to someone of that race was an injury to her feelings by saying racist things in front of her.

But the harm of saying something racist is not that it offends or hurts the feelings of individuals in the maligned race. It isn’t that they say those things that’s the primary problem; it’s that they think them. I’m occasionally mistaken for Jewish, which I’ve discovered when people have tried to make me feel bad by flinging an antisemitic slur at me. What they did is wrong, but not because it hurt my feelings—it didn’t—and not because they expressed hostility to Jews. It’s wrong because racism is not an emotion–it’s a set of beliefs, ones we don’t necessarily know we have. And those beliefs harm our world because anti-semitism is a persistent ideology that erupts periodically into extraordinary violence, and into individual acts of violence on a regular basis.

It isn’t just the feelings; it’s the beliefs. Racism isn’t just about hostility—it’s about beliefs, about Jews as masters of international finance, African-Americans as criminal, Latinx as lazy, Asians as not really American. People are hurt by those beliefs because those beliefs become the basis for how we deliberate on juries, vote, hire, fire, drive, rent.

To frame the problem of racism as though it is a question of individual feelings (racists feel hostility, and objects of racism feel offended) misses the whole point of our shared world being damaged by racism. People who object to racism aren’t doing so because of feeling hurt or offended, but because racism is harmful.